CRITICAL RATIONALISM IN ATHEISM The purpose of this essay is to briefly review the philosophy of Critical Rationalism and present some of its implications for atheism. It is argued that faith is as intellectually respectable and as philosophically well founded as science because both are dependent upon a commitment to (faith in) a principle whose truth cannot be demonstrated. If we think of science as reasoning based on experience, it is thought necessary to show that the method itself is philosophically unassailable in order to differentiate it from faith. I believe it was Hume that first pointed out, however, that reasoning based on experience cannot prove that it is reasonable to reason based on experience, except by an appeal to experience. It is necessary to assume the truth of what is to be proved in order to prove it, which, of course, is no proof at all. If no appeal to experience is made, other difficulties appear. It seems that science is built on a foundation of sand. Based largely on the work of Karl Popper, a number of philosophers have put together a different philosophy of science. This philosophy has a number of names depending on the specific details adhered to, many of which are well beyond the scope of this introduction, as well as being at the limits of my understanding, but for sake of reference I'll call this philosophy "Critical Rationalism." The basis of much philosophy and especially the philosophy of science prior to this century was rationalism of one form or another. The goal of rationalism may be taken as the building of a system of thought founded on premises that cannot be doubted. This goal has proved elusive, to say the least. It is now taken for granted by most philosophers that this goal is impossible to attain, because either the necessary premises can always be questioned, or circular reasoning or an infinite regress are produced. Rationalism assumes that things need to be proved or justified in order to be believed. It is this assumption that has been overturned by Popper. Rather than rationally justifying what is to be believed, he argues that it is necessary, and enough, to expose our hypotheses to testing. Those hypotheses that survive the tests can be provisionally retained. Bartley has generalized this "scientific method" to apply to other forms of belief, and, in place of scientific experiments has substituted criticism. Thus, he and others argue that we are entitled to believe whatever can survive criticism; but it is necessary to seek out and answer the most severe and sophisticated criticism if our beliefs are to be called "rational." Hence the name "Critical Rationalism." Through the process of criticism and revision, the beliefs are refined and improved. There are, of course, innumerable details that need to be considered, and I cannot cover all the bases here. Is it possible to criticize "2+2=4"? Not really; the method is therefore restricted only to "synthetic" statements, and not "analytic" statements. However, there are "synthetic" statements that nevertheless cannot be doubted, such as Wittgenstein's "Cats don't grow on trees." I'm not clear on how these are handled. Is it possible to criticize the philosophy of Critical Rationalism? Yes. In this process there are difficulties with circularity that I cannot address at this time, but I believe these difficulties have been answered. For me the most attractive feature of Critical Rationalism is how it neatly ties in with cultural evolution and certain theories of cognition--all are evolutionary processes. The idea of cultural evolution is that concepts, hypotheses, ideas, etc., in a culture are in competition and that the "fittest" survive, in a method very comparable to the competition and survival of genes. In cognitive science there is a theory that the mind works as a "Darwinian machine," with random generation of variations in thoughts, and selective retention of the best, again, an evolutionary process. Given this development in epistemology, true believers who point to the atheist and say, "You too" are no longer on firm ground. The atheist can reasonably say that he rejects belief in God because that belief cannot effectively answer the best criticism. The atheist, when asked why he "believes in rationality" can safely say that he does so provisionally, and not dogmatically. I think, too, that I now can answer my own most severe doubt. How can I know that I am proceeding wisely in favoring one system of belief over another? In other words, given my limited lifetime, how long do I have to suspend judgment until I can make an informed choice between belief and unbelief? How much evidence do I need to look at, how many books must I read? Must I understand evolution, relativity, and quantum mechanics as well as become an expert in one or more particular faiths? My life will be over before it can be put on the kind of solid philosophical foundation I want it to have. The answer to this is twofold. First, provided that my beliefs are always subject to revision in light of better arguments and new evidence, I can feel confident that I am fully "philosophically entitled" to believe what I believe right now. Given the bible thumper's protectionist attitude towards his own beliefs and his refusal to unevasively face his critics, I don't have to pretend that he is my equal in rationality. I have the properly reasonable attitude towards my beliefs, and he does not towards his. I am in the position of strength, I am on the solid philosophical foundation I seek: provisional belief plus ongoing criticism. Second, I have believed for several years that, because few of us can become authorities in science, the philosophy of religion, etc. (and I certainly don't claim to be an expert), and thereby judge for ourselves the comparative strengths of various positions, much of our most important decision making therefore must be comparatively uninformed decision making. Seemingly, I must take the pronouncements of either scientists or priests on faith, not being able to decide all questions myself. Having no better guide, I am most often compelled to give the nod to tradition and culture when making life-value decisions. I think now that religious belief is "on the run" in a cultural sense. Many have turned away from the old faiths. Many more are believers in name only. I am in line with the dominant culture of this country when I rely on scientists instead of priests. In other words, cultural evolution is proceeding, and the superior concepts and beliefs are ascendant. Congress may open its sessions with a prayer, but then the priest is hustled out the door and they get down to business. In summary, I believe that the philosophy of Critical Rationalism strengthens the skeptic's position by refuting a long-standing counter-argument. Recommended reading: W. W. Bartley, III, The Retreat To Commitment Gerard Radnitzky and W. W. Bartley, III, eds., Evolutionary Epistemology, Rationality, and the Sociology of Knowledge Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker Daniel C. Dennett, Consciousness Explained